USAID v. ALLIANCE FOR OPEN SOCIETY INTERNATIONAL
Supreme Court Cases
570 U.S. 205 (2013)
Opinions
Majority Opinion Author
John Roberts
Majority Participants
Dissenting Participants
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
Syllabus
AGENCY FOR INTERNATIONAL DEVELOPMENT et al. v. ALLIANCE FOR OPEN SOCIETY INTERNATIONAL, INC., et al.
certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
No. 19鈥177.鈥傾rgued May 5, 2020鈥擠ecided June 29, 2020
In the United States Leadership Against HIV/AIDS, Tuberculosis, and Malaria Act of 2003, as relevant here, Congress limited the funding of American and foreign nongovernmental organizations to those with 鈥渁 policy explicitly opposing prostitution and sex trafficking.鈥 22 U. S. C. 搂7631(f). In 2013, that Policy Requirement, as it is known, was held to be an unconstitutional restraint on free speech when applied to American organizations. Agency for Int鈥檒 Development v. Alliance for Open Society Int鈥檒, Inc., 570 U.S. 205. Those American organizations now challenge the requirement鈥檚 constitutionality when applied to their legally distinct foreign affiliates. The District Court held that the Government was prohibited from enforcing the requirement against the foreign affiliates, and the Second Circuit affirmed.
Held: Because plaintiffs鈥 foreign affiliates possess no First Amendment rights, applying the Policy Requirement to them is not unconstitutional. Two bedrock legal principles lead to this conclusion. As a matter of American constitutional law, foreign citizens outside U. S. territory do not possess rights under the U. S. Constitution. See, e.g., Boumediene v. Bush, 553 U.S. 723, 770鈥771. And as a matter of American corporate law, separately incorporated organizations are separate legal units with distinct legal rights and obligations. See, e.g., Dole Food Co. v. Patrickson, 538 U.S. 468, 474鈥475. That conclusion corresponds to Congress鈥檚 historical practice of conditioning funding to foreign organizations, which helps ensure that U. S. foreign aid serves U. S. interests.
Plaintiffs鈥 counterarguments are unpersuasive. First, they claim that because a foreign affiliate鈥檚 policy statement may be attributed to them, American organizations themselves possess a First Amendment right against the Policy Requirement鈥檚 imposition on their foreign affiliates. First Amendment cases involving speech misattribution between formally distinct speakers, see, e.g., Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston, Inc., 515 U.S. 557, 574鈥575, however, are premised on something missing here: Government compulsion to associate with another entity. Even protecting the free speech rights of only those foreign organizations that are closely identified with American organizations would deviate from the fundamental principle that foreign organizations operating abroad do not possess rights under the U. S. Constitution and enmesh the courts in difficult line-drawing exercises. Second, plaintiffs assert that the Court鈥檚 2013 decision encompassed both American organizations and their foreign affiliates. That decision did not facially invalidate the Act鈥檚 funding condition, suggest that the First Amendment requires the Government to exempt plaintiffs鈥 foreign affiliates or other foreign organizations from the Policy Requirement, or purport to override longstanding constitutional law and corporate law principles. Pp. 3鈥9.
911 F.3d 104, reversed.
Kavanaugh, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which Roberts, C. J., and Thomas, Alito, and Gorsuch, JJ., joined. Thomas, J., filed a concurring opinion. Breyer, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which Ginsburg and Sotomayor, JJ., joined. Kagan, J., took no part in the consideration or decision of the case.
NOTICE:鈥俆his opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the United States Reports.鈥僐eaders are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 19鈥177
_________________
AGENCY FOR INTERNATIONAL DEVELOPMENT, et al., PETITIONERS v. ALLIANCE FOR OPEN SOCIETY INTERNATIONAL, INC., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 29, 2020]
Justice Kavanaugh delivered the opinion of the Court.
In 2003, Congress passed and President George W. Bush signed the United States Leadership Against HIV/AIDS, Tuberculosis, and Malaria Act, known as the Leadership Act. 117 Stat. 711, as amended, 22 U. S. C. 搂7601 et seq. Aiming to enhance America鈥檚 response to the ravages of the global HIV/AIDS crisis, the Leadership Act launched 鈥渢he largest international public health program of its kind ever created.鈥 搂7601(29). The Act has helped save an estimated 17 million lives, primarily in Africa, and is widely viewed as the most successful American foreign aid program since the Marshall Plan.
To advance the global relief effort, Congress has allocated billions of dollars to American and foreign nongovernmental organizations that combat HIV/AIDS abroad. As relevant here, Congress sought to fund only those organizations that have, or agree to have, a 鈥減olicy explicitly opposing prostitution and sex trafficking.鈥 搂7631(f ); see also 搂7631(e); 45 CFR 搂89.1 (2019). Congress imposed that condition on funding, known as the Policy Requirement, because Congress found that prostitution and sex trafficking 鈥渁re additional causes of and factors in the spread of the HIV/AIDS epidemic鈥 and that prostitution and sex trafficking 鈥渁re degrading to women and children.鈥 搂7601(23).
Plaintiffs are American nongovernmental organizations that receive Leadership Act funds to fight HIV/AIDS abroad. Plaintiffs have long maintained that they do not want to express their agreement with the American commitment to eradicating prostitution. Plaintiffs consider a public stance of neutrality toward prostitution more helpful to their sensitive work in some parts of the world and also to their full participation in the global efforts to prevent HIV/AIDS.
After enactment of the Leadership Act, plaintiffs challenged the Policy Requirement, alleging that it violated the First Amendment. In 2013, this Court agreed, concluding that the Policy Requirement ran afoul of the free speech principle that the Government 鈥渕ay not deny a benefit to a person on a basis that infringes his constitutionally protected . . . freedom of speech.鈥 Agency for Int鈥檒 Development v. Alliance for Open Society Int鈥檒, Inc., 570 U.S. 205, 214 (2013) (internal quotation marks omitted). Therefore, the Policy Requirement no longer applies to American organizations that receive Leadership Act funds, meaning that American organizations can obtain Leadership Act funds even if they do not have a policy explicitly opposing prostitution and sex trafficking.
But as has been the case since 2003, foreign organizations that receive Leadership Act funds remain subject to the Policy Requirement and still must have a policy explicitly opposing prostitution and sex trafficking. Following this Court鈥檚 2013 decision barring the Government from enforcing the Policy Requirement against American organizations, plaintiffs returned to court, invoking the First Amendment and seeking to bar the Government from enforcing the Policy Requirement against plaintiffs鈥 legally distinct foreign affiliates. The U. S. District Court for the Southern District of New York agreed with plaintiffs and prohibited the Government from enforcing the Policy Requirement against plaintiffs鈥 foreign affiliates. The U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit affirmed. Judge Straub dissented. He described as 鈥渟tartling鈥 the proposition that the First Amendment could extend to foreign organizations operating abroad. 911 F.3d 104, 112 (2018). The Second Circuit鈥檚 decision was stayed pending this Court鈥檚 review, meaning that foreign organizations currently remain subject to the Policy Requirement.
We granted certiorari, 589 U. S. ___ (2019), and now reverse the judgment of the Second Circuit. Plaintiffs鈥 position runs headlong into two bedrock principles of American law.
First, it is long settled as a matter of American constitutional law that foreign citizens outside U. S. territory do not possess rights under the U. S. Constitution. Plaintiffs do not dispute that fundamental principle. Tr. of Oral Arg. 58鈥59; see, e.g., Boumediene v. Bush, 553 U.S. 723, 770鈥771 (2008); Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507, 558鈥559 (2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting); United States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U.S. 259, 265鈥275 (1990); Johnson v. Eisentrager, 339 U.S. 763, 784 (1950); United States ex rel. Turner v. Williams, 194 U.S. 279, 292 (1904); U. S. Const., Preamble.
As the Court has recognized, foreign citizens in the United States may enjoy certain constitutional rights鈥攖o take just one example, the right to due process in a criminal trial. See, e.g., Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U. S., at 270鈥271; Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 210鈥213 (1982); Kwong Hai Chew v. Colding, 344 U.S. 590, 596 (1953); Bridges v. Wixon, 326 U.S. 135, 148 (1945); Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U.S. 356, 369 (1886); cf. Bluman v. Federal Election Comm鈥檔, 800 F. Supp. 2d 281, 286鈥289 (DC 2011), aff 鈥檇, 565 U.S. 1104 (2012). And so too, the Court has ruled that, under some circumstances, foreign citizens in the U. S. Territories鈥攐r in 鈥渁 territory鈥 under the 鈥渋ndefinite鈥 and 鈥渃omplete and total control鈥 and 鈥渨ithin the constant jurisdiction鈥 of the United States鈥攎ay possess certain constitutional rights. Boumediene, 553 U. S., at 755鈥771. But the Court has not allowed foreign citizens outside the United States or such U. S. territory to assert rights under the U. S. Constitution. If the rule were otherwise, actions by American military, intelligence, and law enforcement personnel against foreign organizations or foreign citizens in foreign countries would be constrained by the foreign citizens鈥 purported rights under the U. S. Constitution. That has never been the law. See Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U. S., at 273鈥274; Eisentrager, 339 U. S., at 784.[1]* To be sure, Congress may seek to enact laws that afford foreign citizens abroad statutory rights or causes of action against misconduct by U. S. Government officials, or laws that otherwise regulate the conduct of U. S. officials abroad. See Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U. S., at 275; cf. 10 U. S. C. 搂搂2734(a), 2734a(a); 18 U. S. C. 搂2340A; 21 U. S. C. 搂904; 22 U. S. C. 搂搂2669, 2669鈥1; 42 U. S. C. 搂2000dd; but see 28 U. S. C. 搂2680(k) (Federal Tort Claims Act鈥檚 exception for torts 鈥渁rising in a foreign country鈥). Plaintiffs did not raise any such statutory claim in this case.
Second, it is long settled as a matter of American corporate law that separately incorporated organizations are separate legal units with distinct legal rights and obligations. See Dole Food Co. v. Patrickson, 538 U.S. 468, 474鈥475 (2003); Cedric Kushner Promotions, Ltd. v. King, 533 U.S. 158, 163 (2001); P. Blumberg, K. Strasser, N. Georgakopoulos, & E. Gouvin, Corporate Groups 搂搂6.01, 6.02, 6.05 (2020 Supp.).
Plaintiffs鈥 foreign affiliates were incorporated in other countries and are legally separate from plaintiffs鈥 American organizations. Even though the foreign organizations have affiliated with the American organizations, the foreign organizations remain legally distinct from the American organizations. Plaintiffs do not ask this Court to pierce the corporate veil, nor do they invoke any other relevant exception to that fundamental corporate law principle. Tr. of Oral Arg. 54.
Those two bedrock principles of American constitutional law and American corporate law together lead to a simple conclusion: As foreign organizations operating abroad, plaintiffs鈥 foreign affiliates possess no rights under the First Amendment.
That conclusion corresponds to historical practice regarding American foreign aid. The United States supplies more foreign aid than any other nation in the world. Cong. Research Serv., Foreign Assistance: An Introduction to U. S. Programs and Policy (2020) (Summary). Acting with the President in the legislative process, Congress sometimes imposes conditions on foreign aid. See 22 U. S. C. 搂搂2271, 2272, 2371, 7110(g)(2). Congress may condition funding on a foreign organization鈥檚 ideological commitments鈥攆or example, pro-democracy, pro-women鈥檚 rights, anti-terrorism, pro-religious freedom, anti-sex trafficking, or the like. Doing so helps ensure that U. S. foreign aid serves U. S. interests. By contrast, plaintiffs鈥 approach would throw a constitutional wrench into American foreign policy. In particular, plaintiffs鈥 approach would put Congress in the untenable position of either cutting off certain funding programs altogether, or instead funding foreign organizations that may not align with U. S. values. We see no constitutional justification for the Federal Judiciary to interfere in that fashion with American foreign policy and American aid to foreign organizations.
In short, plaintiffs鈥 foreign affiliates are foreign organizations, and foreign organizations operating abroad have no First Amendment rights.
To overcome that conclusion, plaintiffs advance two main arguments. But neither persuades us.
First, plaintiffs theorize that the foreign affiliates鈥 required statement of policy against prostitution and sex trafficking may be incorrectly attributed to the American organizations. Therefore, the theory goes, the American organizations themselves possess a First Amendment right against imposition of the Policy Requirement on their foreign affiliates.
As support, plaintiffs point to First Amendment cases involving speech misattribution between formally distinct speakers. See, e.g., Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston, Inc., 515 U.S. 557, 574鈥575 (1995); Pacific Gas & Elec. Co. v. Public Util. Comm鈥檔 of Cal., 475 U.S. 1, 15 (1986) (plurality opinion); cf. PruneYard Shopping Center v. Robins, 447 U.S. 74, 87 (1980). But the constitutional issue in those cases arose because the State forced one speaker to host another speaker鈥檚 speech. See Hurley, 515 U. S., at 572鈥573; Pacific Gas, 475 U. S., at 15; cf. PruneYard, 447 U. S., at 85, 87. Here, by contrast, the United States is not forcing plaintiffs to affiliate with foreign organizations. Plaintiffs are free to choose whether to affiliate with foreign organizations and are free to disclaim agreement with the foreign affiliates鈥 required statement of policy. Any alleged misattribution in this case and any effect on the American organizations鈥 message of neutrality toward prostitution stems from their choice to affiliate with foreign organizations, not from U. S. Government compulsion. Because the First Amendment misattribution cases are premised on government compulsion to associate with another entity, those cases do not apply here.
In support of their misattribution argument, plaintiffs also cite Regan v. Taxation With Representation of Wash., 461 U.S. 540, 544鈥545, and n. 6 (1983). But as relevant here, that case simply explained that a speech restriction on a corporate entity did not prevent a separate affiliate from speaking, a point that is not disputed in this case.
We appreciate that plaintiffs would prefer to affiliate with foreign organizations that do not oppose prostitution. But Congress required foreign organizations to oppose prostitution in return for American funding. And plaintiffs cannot export their own First Amendment rights to shield foreign organizations from Congress鈥檚 funding conditions.
Stressing that their position is limited, plaintiffs emphasize that the Court could narrowly decide to protect the free speech rights of only those foreign organizations that are closely identified with American organizations鈥攆or example, those foreign affiliates that share similar names, logos, and brands with American organizations. According to plaintiffs, those 鈥渃losely identified鈥 scenarios greatly increase the risk of misattribution. But again, the First Amendment cases involving speech misattribution arose when the State forced one speaker to host another speaker鈥檚 speech. No compulsion is present here. Moreover, plaintiffs鈥 proposed line-drawing among foreign organizations would blur a clear rule of American law: Foreign organizations operating abroad do not possess rights under the U. S. Constitution. Plaintiffs鈥 carve-out not only would deviate from that fundamental principle, but also would enmesh the courts in difficult line-drawing exercises鈥攈ow closely identified is close enough?鈥攁nd leave courts without any principled basis for making those judgments. We discern no good reason to invent a new and legally unmoored exception to longstanding principles of American constitutional and corporate law.
Second, plaintiffs argue that the Court鈥檚 2013 decision in this case encompassed both plaintiffs鈥 American organizations and their foreign affiliates, meaning that, in plaintiffs鈥 view, the Court has already resolved the issue before us. That is not correct. The plaintiffs in the 2013 case were these same American organizations. It is true that the Court considered the possibility that an American organization could work through affiliates to potentially avoid the burdens of the otherwise-unconstitutional application of the Policy Requirement. But the Court rejected that alternative, which in essence would have compelled the American organizations to affiliate with other organizations. The Court instead ruled that the Policy Requirement may not be applied to plaintiffs鈥 American organizations. Therefore, plaintiffs鈥 current affiliations with foreign organizations are their own choice, not the result of any U. S. Government compulsion.
Stated simply, in the prior decision, the Court did not facially invalidate the Act鈥檚 condition on funding. The Court did not hold or suggest that the First Amendment requires the Government to exempt plaintiffs鈥 foreign affiliates or other foreign organizations from the Policy Requirement. And the Court did not purport to override the longstanding constitutional law principle that foreign organizations operating abroad do not possess constitutional rights, or the elementary corporate law principle that each corporation is a separate legal unit.
The dissent emphasizes that this case concerns 鈥渢he First Amendment rights of American organizations.鈥 Post, at 1 (opinion of Breyer, J.). We respectfully disagree with that characterization of the question presented. The Court鈥檚 prior decision recognized the First Amendment rights of American organizations and held that American organizations do not have to comply with the Policy Requirement. This case instead concerns foreign organizations that are voluntarily affiliated with American organizations. Those foreign organizations are legally separate from the American organizations. And because foreign organizations operating abroad do not possess constitutional rights, those foreign organizations do not have a First Amendment right to disregard the Policy Requirement.
In sum, plaintiffs鈥 foreign affiliates are foreign organizations, and foreign organizations operating abroad possess no rights under the U. S. Constitution. We reverse the judgment of the U. S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit.
It is so ordered.
Justice Kagan took no part in the consideration or decision of this case.
Notes
[1] * As Justice Jackson stated for the Court in Eisentrager: 鈥淚f the Fifth Amendment confers its rights on all the world . . . , the same must be true of the companion civil-rights Amendments, for none of them is limited by its express terms, territorially or as to persons. Such a construction would mean that during military occupation irreconcilable enemy elements, guerrilla fighters, and 鈥榳erewolves鈥 could require the American Judiciary to assure them freedoms of speech, press, and assembly as in the First Amendment, right to bear arms as in the Second, security against 鈥榰nreasonable鈥 searches and seizures as in the Fourth, as well as rights to jury trial as in the Fifth and Sixth Amendments. 鈥淪uch extraterritorial application of organic law would have been so significant an innovation in the practice of governments that, if intended or apprehended, it could scarcely have failed to excite contemporary comment. Not one word can be cited. No decision of this Court supports such a view. Cf. Downes v. Bidwell, 182 U.S. 244. None of the learned commentators on our Constitution has even hinted at it.鈥 339 U. S., at 784鈥785.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 19鈥177
_________________
AGENCY FOR INTERNATIONAL DEVELOPMENT, et al., PETITIONERS v. ALLIANCE FOR OPEN SOCIETY INTERNATIONAL, INC., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 29, 2020]
Justice Thomas, concurring.
I agree with the Court that the Policy Requirement does not violate the First Amendment as applied to 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 foreign affiliates, and I agree that nothing about this Court鈥檚 decision in Agency for Int鈥檒 Development v. Alliance for Open Society Int鈥檒, Inc., 570 U.S. 205 (2013) (AOSI I), suggests otherwise. See ante, at 8鈥9. I write separately to note my continued disagreement with AOSI I and to explain that the Policy Requirement does not violate the First Amendment for a far simpler reason: It does not compel anyone to say anything.
In AOSI I, the Court erred by holding that the Policy Requirement violated 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 First Amendment rights by conditioning their receipt of Leadership Act[1] funds on the affirmation of certain program objectives. 鈥淭he First Amendment does not mandate a viewpoint-neutral government.鈥 AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 221 (Scalia, J., joined by Thomas, J., dissenting). Thus, the Government may require those who seek to carry out federally funded programs to support the Government鈥檚 objectives with regard to those programs. Ibid. After all, the Constitution itself 鈥渋mpos[es] affirmative ideological commitments prerequisite to assisting in the government鈥檚 work.鈥 Id., at 227. It excludes viewpoints such as communism and anarchism, stating that those engaged in government work must swear an oath to support our Constitution鈥檚 republican form of government. See Art. VI, cl. 3.
Moreover, the mere conditioning of funds on 鈥 鈥榯he affirmation of a belief鈥 鈥 tied to the purpose of a government program involves 鈥渘o compulsion at all.鈥 AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 226 (Scalia, J., joined by Thomas, J., dissenting). Such a condition is 鈥渢he reasonable price of admission to a limited government-spending program that each organization remains free to accept or reject.鈥 Ibid. Just as respondents are not compelled to associate with their foreign affiliates, see ante, at 6鈥8, they are not compelled to participate in the Leadership Act program.
The Policy Requirement does not violate the First Amendment, regardless of whether it is applied to respondents, 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 legally distinct foreign affiliates, or any other organization, foreign or domestic. Because the Court properly rejects 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 attempt to extend our erroneous precedent, I join its opinion in full.
Notes
[1] As the Court explains, the United States Leadership Against HIV/AIDS, Tuberculosis, and Malaria Act of 2003 (Leadership Act), 22 U. S. C. 搂7601 et seq., 鈥渁llocate[s] billions of dollars to American and foreign nongovernmental organizations that combat HIV/AIDS abroad.鈥 Ante, at 1.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 19鈥177
_________________
AGENCY FOR INTERNATIONAL DEVELOPMENT, et al., PETITIONERS v. ALLIANCE FOR OPEN SOCIETY INTERNATIONAL, INC., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 29, 2020]
Justice Breyer, with whom Justice Ginsburg and Justice Sotomayor join, dissenting.
The Court, in my view, asks the wrong question and gives the wrong answer. This case is not about the First Amendment rights of foreign organizations. It is about鈥攁nd has always been about鈥攖he First Amendment rights of American organizations.
The last time this case came before us, those American organizations vindicated their constitutional right to speak freely, both at home and abroad. In Agency for Int鈥檒 Development v. Alliance for Open Society Int鈥檒, Inc., 570 U.S. 205 (2013) (AOSI I ), we held that the First Amendment forbids the Government from distorting their speech by requiring, as a condition of receiving federal funds, that they 鈥減ledge allegiance鈥 to a state-sponsored message. Id., at 220.
This time, the question is whether the American organizations enjoy that same constitutional protection against government-compelled distortion when they speak through clearly identified affiliates that have been incorporated overseas. The answer to that question, as I see it, is yes. I dissent from the Court鈥檚 contrary conclusion.
I
To understand the issue now before us, one must appreciate how it got here. Given this litigation鈥檚 lengthy history, that requires a rather detailed look at why this dispute first arose, what we decided in our prior decision (namely, AOSI I ), and where the case proceeded from there.
A
As we explained in AOSI I, the plaintiffs in this action (respondents in this Court then and now) 鈥渁re a group of domestic organizations engaged in combating HIV/AIDS overseas.鈥 Id., at 210. Their lifesaving work spans multiple continents. Id., at 211. For example, respondents run 鈥減rograms aimed at limiting injection drug use in Uzbekistan, Tajikistan, and Kyrgyzstan, preventing mother-to-child HIV transmission in Kenya, and promoting safer sex practices in India.鈥 Ibid. Respondents also counsel high-risk populations such as sex workers, encourage foreign governments to adopt beneficial public policies, and share information about best practices in publications and at conferences. See ibid.; App. 171, 217, 222, 419. To support these international efforts, respondents must make fundraising appeals to donors worldwide. See, e.g., id., at 366, 384, 431鈥433, 457. But crucially for both their mission and for this case, respondents also 鈥渞eceive billions [of dollars] annually in financial assistance from the United States.鈥 AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 210.
One of 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 primary sources of federal funding is the United States Leadership Against HIV/AIDS, Tuberculosis, and Malaria Act of 2003. 117Stat. 711, as amended, 22 U. S. C. 搂7601 et seq. (Leadership Act). Congress enacted the Leadership Act with the goal of creating 鈥渁 鈥榗omprehensive, integrated鈥 strategy to combat HIV/AIDS around the world.鈥 AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 209 (quoting 搂7611(a)). To that end, the statute allocates considerable federal dollars to nongovernmental organizations fighting HIV/AIDS abroad. Id., at 209鈥211.
But Leadership Act funding comes with strings attached. Two, in particular. First, no Leadership Act funds 鈥 鈥榤ay be used to promote or advocate the legalization or practice of prostitution or sex trafficking.鈥 鈥 Id., at 210 (quoting 搂7631(e)). Second, with some exceptions not relevant here, any recipient of Leadership Act funds must have 鈥 鈥榓 policy explicitly opposing prostitution and sex trafficking.鈥 鈥 Id., at 210 (quoting 搂7631(f )). The first condition limiting how Leadership Act funds may be spent has never been challenged in this litigation. Id., at 210. What has driven this decades-long dispute is the second condition, the 鈥淧olicy Requirement鈥 that requires recipients to espouse a government message. Ibid.
Concerned that 鈥渁dopting a policy explicitly opposing prostitution鈥 could 鈥渁lienate certain host governments鈥 and 鈥渕ak[e] it more difficult to work with prostitutes in the fight against HIV/AIDS,鈥 respondents sued. Id., at 211. They asserted that the Policy Requirement put an unconstitutional condition on the receipt of federal funds and was thus unenforceable. Id., at 212. Accordingly, as the case came to us in AOSI I, the question was whether this funding condition violated 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 First Amendment rights. Id., at 211.
B
The answer, we held in AOSI I, was yes. Our reasoning then demands close inspection now.
To begin, we observed in AOSI I that 鈥渢he Policy Requirement would plainly violate the First Amendment鈥 if it operated 鈥渁s a direct regulation of speech.鈥 Id., at 213. Commanding someone to speak a government message contravenes the 鈥渂asic First Amendment principle that 鈥榝reedom of speech prohibits the government from telling people what they must say.鈥 鈥 Ibid. (quoting Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic and Institutional Rights, Inc., 547 U.S. 47, 61 (2006) (FAIR)); see also, e.g., West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624, 642 (1943); Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U.S. 705, 717 (1977).
That the Policy Requirement is a funding condition, rather than a direct command, complicated the analysis in AOSI I but did not change the outcome. True, Congress鈥 Article I spending power 鈥渋ncludes the authority to impose limits on the use of [federal] funds to ensure they are used鈥 as 鈥淐ongress intends,鈥 even conditions that 鈥渕ay affect the recipient鈥檚 exercise of its First Amendment rights.鈥 AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 213鈥214. That is all the first (and unchallenged) Leadership Act condition does by forbidding federal funds from being used to promote prostitution or sex trafficking. See id., at 217鈥218. Congress may not, however, 鈥渓everage funding to regulate speech outside the contours鈥 of the program it has chosen to subsidize. Id., at 214鈥215. That, as we will see, is what the Policy Requirement does鈥攁nd why we held in AOSI I that this second condition violated 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 First Amendment rights.
The constitutional line is whether a funding condition helps 鈥渟pecify the activities Congress wants to subsidize鈥 or instead seeks to 鈥渞each [speech] outside鈥 the federal program. Id., at 214, 217. We recognized in AOSI I that this line 鈥渋s not always self-evident.鈥 Id., at 217. To 鈥渉el[p] illustrate the distinction,鈥 our decision gave two examples from our precedents. Id., at 215.
As an example of what the Government may not do, we pointed to our decision FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., (1984). There, the Government required noncommercial broadcasters receiving federal financial assistance to refrain from editorializing entirely; they could not even 鈥渆stablish [an] 鈥榓ffiliate鈥 organizatio[n]鈥 to editorialize on their behalf 鈥渨ith nonfederal funds.鈥 Id., at 400. By giving a broadcaster no way 鈥渢o make known its views on matters of public importance,鈥 the funding condition in League of Women Voters violated the First Amendment. Id., at 400鈥401. That condition, as we put it in AOSI I, 鈥渨ent beyond鈥 ensuring that federal funds did not subsidize the broadcasters鈥 editorial content and therefore distorted their 鈥渟peech outside the scope of the program.鈥 570 U. S., at 216.
Just the opposite was true in Regan v. Taxation With Representation of Wash., 461 U.S. 540 (1983), the case we cited in AOSI I as an example of what the Government may do. In Regan, a nonprofit group received tax-exempt status as a 搂501(c)(3) organization on the condition that the organization not engage in lobbying. AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 215 (citing Regan, 461 U. S., at 544). Even though this condition on federal financial assistance affected the nonprofit鈥檚 exercise of First Amendment rights, the condition was constitutional because it 鈥渄id not prohibit [the nonprofit] from lobbying Congress altogether.鈥 570 U. S., at 215.
Specifically, the nonprofit in Regan鈥攗nlike the broadcasters in League of Women Voters鈥攚as permitted to establish an affiliate to carry on its lobbying activities as a 搂501(c)(4) organization. AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 215 (citing Regan, 461 U. S., at 544). The nonprofit could thus act (and speak) through two corporate entities: The 搂501(c)(3) organization could get the tax exemption (but not lobby), while the 搂501(c)(4) organization could lobby (but not get the tax exemption). 570 U. S., at 215. Since requiring the nonprofit to adopt this 鈥 鈥榙ual structure鈥 鈥 was not 鈥 鈥榰nduly burdensome,鈥 鈥 the condition in Regan 鈥渄id not deny the [nonprofit] a government benefit 鈥榦n account of its intention to lobby.鈥 鈥 570 U. S., at 215 (quoting Regan, 461 U. S., at 545, and n. 6). The condition was thus constitutional, even though it essentially compelled the nonprofit to affiliate with other organizations. See 570 U. S., at 215.
In AOSI I, we held 鈥渢hat the Policy Requirement falls on the unconstitutional side of the line鈥 separating League of Women Voters (unconstitutional) and Regan (constitutional). 570 U. S., at 217. Like the funding condition in League of Women Voters, we explained, the Policy Requirement affects protected speech outside the scope of the federal program. 570 U. S., at 218. 鈥淏y requiring recipients to profess a specific belief,鈥 it 鈥済oes beyond defining鈥 the program 鈥渢o defining the recipient鈥 in the eyes of their global audience. Ibid. Respondents cannot 鈥渁vow [a] belief dictated by鈥 the Government 鈥渨hen spending Leadership Act funds, and then turn around and assert a contrary belief, or claim neutrality,鈥 when acting on their 鈥渙wn time and dime.鈥 Ibid. The Policy Requirement thus conditioned funding on an across-the-board distortion of 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 message. See ibid.
We further explained in AOSI I鈥攁nd this is critical鈥攚hy we could not accept the Government鈥檚 suggestion that the case was just a redux of Regan. In AOSI I, the Government suggested a similar 鈥渄ual-structure鈥 solution to the First Amendment problem. Like the nonprofit in Regan, the Government noted, respondents could act (and speak) through two corporate entities: One organization could receive Leadership Act funds on 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 behalf (and comply with the Policy Requirement), while a legally separate affiliate could communicate 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 preferred message (and not receive Leadership Act funds)鈥攐r vice versa. AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 219. True enough. But we rejected the Government鈥檚 argument all the same.
Why did we reject it? Because corporate formalities do nothing to ward off speech distortion where鈥攍ike AOSI I, but unlike Regan鈥攖he Government has required a speaker to 鈥渆spouse a specific belief as its own.鈥 570 U. S., at 219. 鈥淚f the affiliate is distinct from the recipient,鈥 we reasoned, 鈥渢he arrangement does not afford a means for the recipient to express its 产别濒颈别蹿蝉.鈥 Ibid. And if 鈥渢he affiliate is more clearly identified with the recipient, the recipient can express those beliefs only at the price of evident hypocrisy.鈥 Ibid. With respect to the latter situation, in other words, compelling a recipient to disavow a message involuntarily uttered by its clearly identified affiliate is forced hypocrisy, not free speech. See ibid.
In sum, the Policy Requirement conditioned federal funds on an unavoidable and irreversible distortion of 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 protected speech. We therefore held in AOSI I that the Policy Requirement 鈥渧iolates the First Amendment and cannot be sustained.鈥 Id., at 221.
C
On remand from our decision, the District Court did what district courts ought to do. It 鈥渢ailor[ed] 鈥榯he scope of the remedy鈥 to fit 鈥榯he nature and extent of the constitutional violation鈥 鈥 that we identified in AOSI I. Hills v. Gautreaux, 425 U.S. 284, 294 (1976) (quoting Milliken v. Bradley, 418 U.S. 717, 744 (1974)).
The District Court, like our Court, recognized that 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 work鈥攁nd with it their protected speech鈥攈as a global reach. But respondents, it turns out, use different organizational structures to deliver services in different places. 106 F. Supp. 3d 355, 360鈥361 (SDNY 2015). Sometimes, particularly when foreign governments (or our own government) require, respondents operate through legally separate affiliates incorporated abroad. Ibid.; see also, e.g., App. 368, 373鈥375.
In the District Court鈥檚 view, those corporate formalities did not meaningfully change the First Amendment calculus. See 106 F. Supp. 3d, at 360鈥361. Respondents, together with their affiliates, convey a clear, consistent message to high-risk populations, government officials, healthcare professionals, prospective employees, and private donors across the globe. See, e.g., App. 370鈥371, 391, 460鈥461. They share the same name, logo, and branding鈥攁ll of which use identical colors, fonts, and imagery. See, e.g., id., at 445鈥455. They adhere to shared values, work towards common goals, and coordinate their collective message. See, e.g., id., at 385鈥386, 404鈥429. To an outside observer, respondents and their affiliates are a single, cohesive unit. They speak as one.
The District Court consequently concluded that imposing the Policy Requirement on 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 affiliates鈥攚herever they happen to have been incorporated鈥攚ould force respondents to 鈥渆xpres[s] contrary positions on the same matter through [their] different organizational components.鈥 106 F. Supp. 3d, at 361. To prevent that from happening, and in keeping with the principles we set forth in AOSI I, the District Court enjoined enforcement of the Policy Requirement against respondents and their clearly identified affiliates, including affiliates that were incorporated overseas. Id., at 363. The District Court thought that remedial order necessary to protect 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 own First Amendment rights鈥攔ights that, as American organizations, respondents unquestionably have. Id., at 361.
The Court of Appeals understood the District Court鈥檚 order that way, too. 鈥淭he narrow issue before鈥 us, the Court of Appeals explained, 鈥渋s whether applying the Policy Requirement to [谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥橾 closely aligned foreign affiliates violates [谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥橾 own First Amendment rights.鈥 911 F.3d 104, 109 (CA2 2018). The Court of Appeals held that the answer was yes and affirmed on that basis. Ibid. We granted certiorari to review the Court of Appeals鈥 decision.
II
The road has been long, but we have arrived at the specific question now before us: whether enforcing the Policy Requirement against 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 clearly identified foreign affiliates violates 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 own First Amendment rights. Like the District Court and the Court of Appeals, I believe the answer is yes.
Our reasoning in AOSI I, along with the body of precedent on which it relied, should decide this case. Just as compelling a clearly identified domestic affiliate to espouse a government message distorts 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 own protected speech, AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 219, so too does compelling a clearly identified foreign affiliate to espouse the same government message. Either way, federal funding conditioned on that affirmative avowal of belief comes at an unconstitutionally high 鈥減rice of evident hypocrisy.鈥 Ibid.
Properly understood, our speech-misattribution cases鈥攊n particular Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston, Inc., 515 U.S. 557 (1995)鈥攃onfirm that common-sense conclusion. Any other result would undermine First Amendment protections for the countless American speakers who address audiences overseas.
A
Respondents should prevail here for the same reasons they prevailed in AOSI I. When respondents speak through legally separate but clearly identified affiliates, we held, that speech is attributed to respondents for First Amendment purposes. AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 219. So when the Government demands as a condition of federal funding that their clearly identified affiliate 鈥渆spouse a specific belief as its own,鈥 respondents may express a contrary view through some other corporate channel only on pain of appearing hypocritical. Ibid. Leveraging Congress鈥 Article I spending power to distort 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 protected speech in this way therefore violates 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 First Amendment rights鈥攚hatever else might be said about the affiliate鈥檚 own First Amendment rights (or asserted lack thereof ). Ibid.
These principles apply with full force to the dispute now before us. Respondents and their affiliates receive federal funding to fight HIV/AIDS overseas. What has been at stake in this case from the beginning, then, is protected speech often aimed at audiences abroad. Our decision in AOSI I shielded 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 global message from government-compelled distortion in the eyes of those foreign audiences, as well as listeners here at home. Ibid. Yet in the wake of our ruling, respondents have continued to suffer that exact same First Amendment harm.
True, 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 international mission sometimes requires that they convey their message through affiliates incorporated in far-off countries, rather than registered here at home. But so what? Audiences everywhere attribute speech based on whom they perceive to be speaking, not on corporate paperwork they will never see. What mattered in AOSI I was thus how 鈥渃learly identified鈥 the affiliates were with respondents, not the fact that the affiliates were incorporated as separate legal entities. Ibid. And what matters now is once again how 鈥渃learly identified鈥 the affiliates are with respondents, not the fact that the affiliates were incorporated as foreign legal entities.
The First Amendment question therefore hinges, as it did before, on what an objective observer sees, hears, and understands when respondents speak through their foreign affiliates. As to that, not even the Government meaningfully disputes that respondents and their foreign affiliates are clearly identified with one another. Their appearances are the same. Their goals are the same. Their values are the same. Their message is the same. Leveraging Congress鈥 spending power to demand speech from 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 foreign affiliates distorts that shared message鈥攁nd violates 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 First Amendment rights. So while respondents and their clearly identified foreign affiliates may be technically different entities with respect to such matters as contracts, taxes, and torts, they are constitutionally the same speaker when it comes to the protected speech at issue in this case.
This two-entities-one-speaker principle is an established part of our First Amendment jurisprudence. Take Regan. To refresh, in that case we upheld a ban on engaging in certain protected speech (lobbying) that the federal tax code imposed on a nonprofit鈥檚 搂501(c)(3) organization because the nonprofit could still speak through a separate 搂501(c)(4) organization. See 461 U. S., at 544. Put simply, one speaker (the nonprofit) could act (and speak) through two legally separate entities (the 搂501(c)(3) and 搂501(c)(4) organizations).
Recall also our similar observation in League of Women Voters. There we noted that a funding condition鈥檚 ban on editorializing would have been constitutional if, in contrast to the law at issue, the statute let noncommercial broadcasters 鈥渕ake known鈥 their 鈥渧iews on matters of public importance鈥 by speaking through legally separate 鈥渆ditorializing affiliate[s].鈥 468 U. S., at 400. Once again, we made clear that a single speaker can act (and speak) through two legally separate entities. But because the speaker in League of Women Voters was not free to do so, we held that the Government鈥檚 funding condition violated the First Amendment. Id., at 400鈥401.
Regan and League of Women Voters are far from our only precedents recognizing this firmly entrenched First Amendment principle. See Legal Services Corporation v. Velazquez, 531 U.S. 533, 546 (2001) (observing that organizational affiliates may provide 鈥渁lternative channel[s] for expression鈥 by a single speaker); Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 196鈥198 (1991) (similar). We reiterated that rule once again in AOSI I. See 570 U. S., at 215鈥217, 219.
Thus, in the First Amendment context, the corporate veil is not an iron curtain. Just the opposite. We attribute speech across corporate lines all the time.
Rightly so. When a funding condition restricts speech, this familiar framework often avoids First Amendment problems by allowing 鈥渁lternative channel[s]鈥 for speakers to express themselves. Velazquez, 531 U. S., at 546. And when a funding condition compels speech, the same logic leads to a similarly sensible result: The Government may not require you to speak out of both sides of your mouth, even if each side happens to have been incorporated as a separate legal entity. See AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 219.
A contrary approach would have led to a rather surprising result in AOSI I. Assume for a moment that the Policy Requirement simply commanded 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 clearly identified affiliates to speak鈥攖he kind of 鈥渄irect regulation of speech鈥 that we said 鈥渨ould plainly violate the First Amendment,鈥 id., at 213. Treating corporate lines as ironclad would mean that respondents could not object to that direct distortion of their own message. Under all the cases just discussed, however, that cannot be right. And as discussed below, it is equally wrong under our cases involving speech misattribution.
B
The First Amendment protects speakers from government compulsion that is likely to cause an audience to mistake someone else鈥檚 message for the speaker鈥檚 own views. See, e.g., Hurley, 515 U. S., at 572鈥573; Pacific Gas & Elec. Co. v. Public Util. Comm鈥檔 of Cal., 475 U.S. 1, 15鈥16 (1986). Corporate separation makes no meaningful difference in this speech-misattribution context, either.
Consider our unanimous decision in Hurley. In that case, a group called the South Boston Allied War Veterans Council organized a parade. 515 U. S., at 560. The Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston鈥攁 separate group who called themselves 鈥淕LIB鈥 for short鈥攚anted to participate. Id., at 561. After the Veterans Council said no, GLIB obtained a court order directing the Veterans Council to let GLIB march in the parade. Id., at 561鈥562. Recognizing that 鈥渆very participating unit affects the message conveyed by the parade organizers,鈥 we held in Hurley that the order distorted the Veterans Council鈥檚 protected speech. Id., at 572鈥573. Because GLIB wanted to 鈥渃arr[y] its own banner鈥 with its own message, and because onlookers would understand GLIB as 鈥渃ontribut[ing] something to鈥 the parade鈥檚 鈥渃ommon theme,鈥 the order 鈥渆ssentially requir[ed]鈥 the Veterans Council 鈥渢o alter the expressive content of their parade.鈥 Id., at 572鈥573, 576. That violated the First Amendment. Id., at 573.
The First Amendment violation in this case is even more apparent. In Hurley, the Veterans Council had merely 鈥渃ombin[ed] multifarious voices鈥 of disparate groups without bothering to 鈥渋solate an exact message,鈥 yet the First Amendment protected its message from government-compelled distortion all the same. Id., at 569. Respondents in this case have done the Veterans Council one better. They have carefully constructed a cogent message and marshaled their clearly identified foreign affiliates to express it across the globe. See supra, at 7鈥8, 10.
Furthermore, in Hurley we could only speculate about what GLIB鈥檚 exact message was and why the Veterans Council did not want to be associated with it. See 515 U. S., at 574鈥575. But here we know exactly what the challenged message is (鈥渁 policy explicitly opposing prostitution and sex trafficking鈥) and why respondents don鈥檛 want to be associated with it (the message, among other things, purportedly 鈥 鈥榮tigmatizes one of the very groups whose trust [respondents] must earn to conduct effective HIV/AIDS prevention鈥 鈥). 22 U. S. C. 搂7631(f ); Brief for Respondents 11. For that reason as well, the First Amendment injury in this case is open, obvious, and unusually well defined.
True, Hurley and our other speech-misattribution cases dealt with a speaker complaining about being forced to affiliate with someone else鈥檚 speech, rather than (as here) their pre-existing affiliate being forced to speak. Cf. ante, at 6. But that factual distinction makes no constitutional difference. From a First Amendment perspective, the latter situation is just as bad or even worse, not better.
Consider Hurley again. If, rather than requiring the Veterans Council to let GLIB march while carrying its banner, the state court had ordered a previously invited marcher (or worse still, all previously invited marchers) to display GLIB鈥檚 banner, the Veterans Council would have prevailed all the same. By compelling speech from an existing affiliate (or all of them), that order would have required, even more brazenly, that the Veterans Council 鈥渁lter the expressive content of their parade鈥 in violation of the Veterans Council鈥檚 First Amendment rights. 515 U. S., at 572鈥573. So too if the state court had decreed that GLIB鈥檚 banner must adorn a horse, oxen, or for that matter R2鈥揇2, a robot鈥攅ven though those entities lack their own First Amendment rights. Whether the transmitter of a speaker鈥檚 protected message does (or does not) have its own First Amendment rights is beside the point. Cf. Wooley, 430 U. S., at 717 (prohibiting New Hampshire from requiring that the state motto adorn a driver鈥檚 car, even though cars do not have First Amendment rights).
There is a reason why, until today, we had not confronted a case like the one just described. Cf. ante, at 6. Requiring someone to host another person鈥檚 speech is often a perfectly legitimate thing for the Government to do. See, e.g., FAIR, 547 U. S., at 65 (holding that the Government may require law schools to host speech from military recruiters); PruneYard Shopping Center v. Robins, 447 U.S. 74, 87鈥88 (1980) (holding that the Government may require the owner of a private shopping mall to host speech from politically minded pamphleteers). Even the court order at issue in Hurley was an understandable (though unconstitutional) application of a 鈥渧enerable鈥 civil rights law. See 515 U. S., at 571. But because compelling people to profess a belief they do not hold is almost always unconstitutional, see AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 213, the Government rarely dares try. The Government鈥檚 well-founded reticence in the past is no reason to bless its boldness at present.
Bottom line: The critical question here, as in Hurley, is simply whether the Government has demanded a profession of belief that will distort the speaker鈥檚 message. How the Government causes that distortion makes no constitutional difference. And as explained, enforcing the Policy Requirement against 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 clearly identified foreign affiliates would plainly distort 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 message. See supra, at 7鈥8, 10. That violates 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 First Amendment rights.
C
So far as I am aware, we have never before held that an American speaker forfeits First Amendment protection when it speaks though foreign affiliates to reach audiences overseas. It is easy to understand why.
Many American news networks operate through clearly identified foreign affiliates when speaking abroad. Viewers attribute that speech to an American speaker: the network. That is the whole point of using clearly identified foreign affiliates. For example, CNN speaks to audiences in the Philippines, Brazil, Indonesia, and other countries using foreign affiliates, usually styled as CNN Philippines, CNN Brazil, CNN Indonesia, and so on. See CNN Worldwide Fact Sheet (Oct. 2019), https:// cnnpressroom.blogs.cnn.com/cnn-fact-sheet. But does that corporate structure mean that CNN鈥i.e., the American parent organization鈥攈as no First Amendment protection against a Government effort to, say, prevent CNN Mexico from covering the fatal shooting of a Mexican child by a U. S. Border Patrol agent? Cf. 贬别谤苍谩苍诲别锄 v. Mesa, 589 U. S. ___ (2020) (贬别谤苍谩苍诲别锄 II ). Or to compel CNN Mexico to run a different story, perhaps one produced by Government personnel, that praises American policy at the border?
We should be highly skeptical. If the Government commandeered CNN鈥檚 clearly identified foreign affiliate in these or similar ways, whether by monetary pressure or some other means, CNN should have constitutional recourse. Some critical foreign policy interests might complicate the First Amendment calculus鈥攕ay, a wartime need to keep future battle plans secret. But nothing like that is present here. And it is difficult to accept the notion that the First Amendment permits the Government to suppress, compel, or otherwise distort any and all American speech transmitted abroad through a clearly identified foreign affiliate.
III
The upshot is: (1) The messages at issue here belong to American speakers; (2) clearly identified foreign affiliates are a critical means of conveying those messages overseas; and (3) enforcing the Policy Requirement against those affiliates distorts 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 own protected speech鈥攁nd thus violates 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 own First Amendment rights.
The majority justifies its contrary result on three main grounds, two of which it says are 鈥渂edrock principles鈥 of American law. See ante, at 3鈥6, 8. I do not find these arguments persuasive.
A
The first 鈥渂edrock principle鈥 on which the majority relies is the supposedly long-settled, across-the-board rule 鈥渢hat foreign citizens outside U. S. territory do not possess rights under the U. S. Constitution.鈥 Ante, at 3. That sweeping assertion is neither relevant to this case nor correct on the law.
It is not relevant because, as I have said, this case does not concern the constitutional rights of foreign organizations. This case concerns the constitutional rights of American organizations. Every respondent here is鈥攁nd has always been鈥擜merican. AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 210; see also Brief for Petitioners 7, 19 (acknowledging as much). No foreign entities are party to this case, and respondents have never claimed that the Policy Requirement violates anyone鈥檚 First Amendment rights apart from their own. Both the District Court and the Court of Appeals decided the case on that basis. The question before us is clear: whether the First Amendment protects Americans when they speak through clearly identified foreign affiliates to reach audiences overseas. See supra, at 8. Whether the foreign affiliates themselves have their own First Amendment rights is not at issue. See Brief for Respondents 36, n. 3.
Even taken on its own terms, the majority鈥檚 blanket assertion about the extraterritorial reach of our Constitution does not reflect the current state of the law. The idea that foreign citizens abroad never have constitutional rights is not a 鈥渂edrock鈥 legal principle. At most, one might say that they are unlikely to enjoy very often extraterritorial protection under the Constitution. Or one might say that the matter is undecided. But this Court has studiously avoided establishing an absolute rule that forecloses that protection in all circumstances.
In 贬别谤苍谩苍诲别锄 v. Mesa, 582 U. S. ___ (2017) (per curiam) (贬别谤苍谩苍诲别锄 I ), for example, we specifically declined to decide the 鈥渟ensitive鈥 question whether, on the facts then before us, a Mexican citizen standing on Mexican soil had Fourth Amendment rights鈥攑recisely because the answer to that extraterritoriality question 鈥渕ay have consequences that are far reaching.鈥 Id., at ___ (slip op., at 5). 贬别谤苍谩苍诲别锄 later came to this Court again, and we decided the case on alternative grounds. See 贬别谤苍谩苍诲别锄 II, 589 U. S., at ___鈥揰__ (slip op., at 19鈥20). Were the majority鈥檚 categorical rule of (non)extraterritoriality etched in stone, we could have disposed of 贬别谤苍谩苍诲别锄 the first time around in a few short sentences.
Nor do the cases that the majority cites support an absolute rule. See ante, at 3. The exhaustive review of our precedents that we conducted in Boumediene v. Bush, 553 U.S. 723 (2008), pointed to the opposite conclusion. In Boumediene, we rejected the Government鈥檚 argument that our decision in Johnson v. Eisentrager, 339 U.S. 763 (1950), 鈥渁dopted a formalistic鈥 test 鈥渇or determining the reach鈥 of constitutional protection to foreign citizens on foreign soil. 553 U. S., at 762. This is to say, we rejected the position that the majority propounds today. See ante, at 4, and n. (quoting Eisentrager at length). Its 鈥渃onstricted reading鈥 of Eisentrager and our other precedents is not the law. See Boumediene, 553 U. S., at 764; see also, e.g., Neuman, Understanding Global Due Process, 23 Geo. Immigration L. J. 365, 400 (2009) (describing our cases as rejecting any absolute view).
The law, we confirmed in Boumediene, is that constitutional 鈥渜uestions of extraterritoriality turn on objective factors and practical concerns鈥 present in a given case, 鈥渘ot formalism鈥 of the sort the majority invokes today. 553 U. S., at 764. Those considerations include the extent of de facto U. S. Government control (if any) over foreign territory. See ante, at 4. But they also include the nature of the constitutional protection sought, how feasible extending it would be in a given case, and the foreign citizen鈥檚 status vis-脿-vis the United States, among other pertinent circumstances that might arise. 553 U. S., at 766; see also United States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U.S. 259, 278 (1990) (Kennedy, J., concurring) (providing the decisive fifth vote for rejecting a foreign citizen鈥檚 claim to constitutional protection on foreign soil outside U. S. control because 鈥淸t]he conditions and considerations of this case would make adherence to the Fourth Amendment鈥檚 warrant requirement impracticable and anomalous鈥 (emphasis added)). Our precedents reject absolutism. Indeed, even our most sweeping statements about foreign citizens鈥 (lack of ) constitutional rights while outside U. S. Territory have come with limits. See, e.g., Landon v. Plasencia, 459 U.S. 21, 32 (1982) (noting that 鈥渁n alien seeking initial admission to鈥 this country 鈥渉as no constitutional rights regarding his application鈥 (emphasis added)); Kleindienst v. Mandel, 408 U.S. 753, 762 (1972) (similar).
There is wisdom in our past restraint. Situations where a foreign citizen outside U. S. Territory might fairly assert constitutional rights are not difficult to imagine. Long-term permanent residents are 鈥渇oreign citizens.鈥 Does the Constitution therefore allow American officials to assault them at will while 鈥渙utside U. S. territory鈥? Many international students attend college in the United States. Does the First Amendment permit a public university to revoke their admission based on an unpopular political stance they took on social media while home for the summer? Foreign citizens who have never set foot in the United States, for that matter, often protest when Presidents travel overseas. Does that mean Secret Service agents can, consistent with our Constitution, seriously injure peaceful protestors abroad without any justification?
We have never purported to give a single 鈥渂edrock鈥 answer to these or myriad other extraterritoriality questions that might arise in the future. To purport to do so today, in a case where the question is not presented and where the matter is not briefed, is in my view a serious mistake.
And there is no need to set forth an absolute rule here. Respondents have conceded that their foreign affiliates lack First Amendment rights of their own while acting abroad. See ante, at 3. If in spite of everything else, the majority considers this point material to its decision, all that need be said is: 鈥淲e accept 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 concession and proceed on that basis.鈥 To say so much more 鈥渞un[s] contrary to the fundamental principal of judicial restraint,鈥 a principle that applies with particular force to constitutional interpretation. Washington State Grange v. Washington State Republican Party, 552 U.S. 442, 450 (2008); see also, e.g., Lyng v. Northwest Indian Cemetery Protective Assn., 485 U.S. 439, 445 (1988); Three Affiliated Tribes of Fort Berthold Reservation v. Wold Engineering, P. C., 467 U.S. 138, 158 (1984); United States v. Raines, 362 U.S. 17, 21 (1960); Liverpool, New York & Philadelphia S. S. Co. v. Commissioners of Emigration, 113 U.S. 33, 39 (1885).
B
The majority鈥檚 second supposedly 鈥渂edrock principle鈥 is that 鈥渟eparately incorporated organizations are separate legal units with distinct legal rights and obligations.鈥 Ante, at 5. Sometimes true, sometimes not. This baseline rule gives way in many contexts, and our First Amendment precedents (including AOSI I ) refute any suggestion that a workaday principle of corporate law somehow resolves the constitutional issue here in dispute.
As the majority acknowledges, corporate law itself permits courts to pierce or otherwise disregard the corporate veil in a variety of circumstances. See ante, at 5. Those narrow exceptions, however, are not the only time the law looks past corporate formalities. For instance, we have treated 鈥渟everal nominally separate business entities鈥 as 鈥渁 single employer鈥 for purposes of federal labor law. Radio & Television Technicians v. Broadcast Service of Mobile, Inc., 380 U.S. 255, 256 (1965) (per curiam). Earlier this Term, we reaffirmed that one corporate entity may sometimes invoke the right of another, legally separate entity to compel arbitration. See GE Energy Power Conversion France SAS v. Outokumpu Stainless USA, LLC, 590 U. S. ___, ___ (2020) (slip op., at 4). And these are far from the only relevant examples. See, e.g., American Needle, Inc. v. National Football League, 560 U.S. 183, 196 (2010) (observing that, in many antitrust cases, corporate formalities are 鈥渘ot determinative鈥).
More to the point, our First Amendment precedents leave no doubt that corporate formalities have little to say about the issue now before us. We have made clear again and again (and again) that speech may be attributed across corporate lines in the First Amendment context鈥攊ncluding in our previous opinion in this very case. See AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 219 (concluding that speech uttered involuntarily by legally separate affiliates may be attributed to respondents if the affiliates are 鈥渃learly identified鈥 with respondents); League of Women Voters, 468 U. S., at 400 (observing that funding conditions that restrict speech can survive constitutional scrutiny if the speaker may 鈥渕ake known its views on matters of public importance through鈥 a legally separate affiliate鈥攁nd if not, not); Regan, 461 U. S., at 544 (similar); Rust, 500 U. S., at 196鈥198 (similar); Velazquez, 531 U. S., at 546鈥547 (similar). And these precedents further establish that merely requiring speakers to work through affiliates is 鈥渘ot unduly burdensome鈥 and can therefore cure, rather than create, First Amendment concerns. Regan, 461 U. S., at 545, n. 6. Contra, ante, at 8 (suggesting that such a requirement would be unconstitutional). Small wonder the majority can muster only two context-specific and statute-specific cases鈥攐ne addressing the Foreign Sovereign Immunities Act, the other involving the Racketeer Influence and Corrupt Organizations Act鈥攁s affirmative support for its conclusion that corporate formalities somehow control the First Amendment question before us. See ante, at 5 (citing Dole Food Co. v. Patrickson, 538 U.S. 468 (2003), and Cedric Kushner Promotions, Ltd. v. King, 533 U.S. 158 (2001)).
The majority also attempts to distinguish the facts before us now from the facts that were before us last time. It asserts that, in contrast to the affiliations we addressed in AOSI I, 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 鈥渃urrent affiliations with foreign organizations are their own choice.鈥 Ante, at 8. There are two problems with this. First, the description is not accurate. Foreign governments鈥攁nd increasingly, the U. S. Government鈥攐ften require respondents to work through foreign affiliates. See, e.g., App. 368, 373鈥375. Second, even if 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 associations with foreign affiliates were voluntary, it would not solve the First Amendment problem.
In Wooley, for example, it was the drivers鈥 choice to own a car, but that did not mean they could be compelled to convey the Government鈥檚 message on their car鈥檚 license plate. See 430 U. S., at 717. And in Hurley, as explained, the Government would have violated the parade organizers鈥 First Amendment rights just the same if it had compelled speech from a previously invited marcher, whether human, animal, or droid. See supra, at 13鈥14. Can the majority really mean to suggest otherwise, simply because the parade organizers鈥 decision to invite the marcher in the first place was 鈥渢heir own choice鈥?
C
The majority also makes two practical arguments, but neither justifies the First Amendment costs of its decision.
The majority first says that a ruling in 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 favor would disrupt American foreign policy by requiring the Government to fund 鈥渙rganizations that may not align with U. S. values.鈥 Ante, at 6. We dismissed this same concern in AOSI I. The Policy Requirement, we explained, does not merely help the Government 鈥渆nlist the assistance of those with whom it already agrees.鈥 AOSI I, 570 U. S., at 218. It pressures funding recipients 鈥to adopt a particular belief.鈥 Ibid. (emphasis added). All that is at stake here, in other words, is whether the Government may leverage the power of the purse to win converts to its cause. That bare desire to regulate protected speech is far from any foreign policy interest that could conceivably overcome a speaker鈥檚 First Amendment right to convey its message free from government-compelled distortion. Cf. New York Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. 713 (1971) (per curiam).
The majority also fears that determining whether Government action creates a risk of speech misattribution (and with it speech distortion) is a 鈥渓egally unmoored鈥 standard rife with 鈥渄ifficult line-drawing exercises.鈥 Ante, at 8. But we have drawn just this kind of line many times. See, e.g., PruneYard, 447 U. S., at 87 (holding that 鈥渧iews expressed by members of the public鈥 in a privately owned shopping mall 鈥渨ill not likely be identified with those of the owner鈥); Hurley, 515 U. S., at 572 (holding that a marcher鈥檚 message will likely be attributed to the parade organizer鈥檚, since 鈥渆very participating unit鈥 in a parade 鈥渁ffects the [overall] message鈥); FAIR, 547 U. S., at 65 (holding that nothing about having military recruiters on campus 鈥渟uggests that law schools agree with any speech by recruiters鈥). I should think that the price of making difficult judgment calls is well worth paying to protect First Amendment rights. See McCutcheon v. Federal Election Comm鈥檔, 572 U.S. 185, 209 (2014); Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551, 570 (1972). And 鈥渙n the facts presented in this case,鈥 at any rate, 鈥渢he answer is clear.鈥 Id., at 570. Enforcing the Policy Requirement violates 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 First Amendment rights, just as it did before.
*鈥冣赌*鈥冣赌*
The Court today concludes that 谤别蝉辫辞苍诲别苍迟蝉鈥 foreign affiliates 鈥渄o not have a First Amendment right to disregard the Policy Requirement.鈥 Ante, at 9. Respondents have never argued otherwise. Rather, throughout this litigation they have asserted their own First Amendment right to speak their mind, rather than the Government鈥檚 message. Here, respondents claim First Amendment protection when they speak through foreign affiliates to address audiences abroad. By denying respondents that protection, I fear the Court鈥檚 decision will seriously impede the countless American speakers who communicate overseas in a similar way. That weakens the marketplace of ideas at a time when the value of that marketplace for Americans, and for others, reaches well beyond our shores. With respect, I dissent.