蜜桃直播

Table of Contents

Your yard, your rights: Lawn signs and the First Amendment

Research & Learn

Local governments may regulate sign displays in some ways, but the First Amendment protects residents from viewpoint-based or arbitrary restrictions. 

(Last Updated: June 9, 2025)

Dozens of election campaign yard signs planted in grass in Suwanee, Georgia

Whether they鈥檙e supporting a political candidate, congratulating a recent high school graduate, cheering a local sports team, or celebrating a holiday, Americans often use lawn signs to express themselves. But many local governments try to restrict the type or number of signs residents can display, as well as how long signs can stay up. Even worse, officials sometimes selectively enforce these rules against signs with messages they dislike. 

Thankfully, the First Amendment prohibits local governments from enforcing arbitrary restrictions on your right to display yard signs. Because signs by definition communicate messages 鈥 through words, images, or symbols 鈥 they constitute a form of speech protected by the First Amendment. 

Yard signs are a form of expression fully protected by the First Amendment. 

This explainer will explore the general legal framework that court decisions have established for restrictions on personal yard signs, and by extension flags, which local governments often also regulate under sign ordinances. (Restrictions on commercial signs fall under a different constitutional standard and are outside this explainer鈥檚 scope.)

Legal analysis of yard sign restrictions usually begins in earnest with the following question: Does the sign ordinance attempt to regulate signs based on content, or is it content-neutral? The answer determines how strictly the court will review the ordinance.

Content-based restrictions on lawn signs

If an ordinance treats signs differently based on their topic or message, it鈥檚 a content-based restriction unlikely to pass constitutional muster.

The Supreme Court鈥檚 decision in Reed v. Town of Gilbert illustrates this point. In that case, a church without a permanent location often put up signs early on Saturdays about where it would hold Sunday services. The town twice cited the church and its pastor for violating the municipal sign code, which regulated what signs could be posted anywhere in town, including on private property. The code allowed 鈥渢emporary directional signs鈥 related to an event only 12 hours before and 1 hour after the event. In contrast, 鈥減olitical signs鈥 could remain on display for up to 60 days before a primary election and up to 15 days after a general election, while 鈥渋deological signs鈥 had no durational limits at all.

A municipal court judge in New Jersey ordered homeowner Andrea Dick to remove banners containing the phrase 鈥淔uck Biden鈥 from her property or face a fine. The decision was widely derided as unconstitutional and the charges were dropped.

VICTORY: On First Amendment grounds, NJ woman鈥檚 鈥楩uck Biden鈥 flags free to fly another day

Andrea Dick鈥檚 lawsuit proceeds after defeating township鈥檚 motion to dismiss 鈥 paving the way toward recovery after being ordered to remove political banners criticizing Joe Biden.

Read More

The Supreme Court held the sign code was content-based on its face because it regulated signs differently based on the message communicated. Even if the town wasn鈥檛 trying to suppress any particular viewpoint, its differential treatment of signs based on their content was enough to trigger strict scrutiny 鈥 the most exacting standard of judicial review.

Strict scrutiny requires the government to prove its regulation furthers a compelling interest and is narrowly tailored to achieving that interest, including by using the least speech-restrictive means to do so. The test is designed to protect against overly expansive speech regulations and politically expedient justifications for restricting speech.

For the vast majority of laws, strict scrutiny is a death sentence.

That was true of the Town of Gilbert鈥檚 sign code. The town cited two interests, aesthetics and traffic safety 鈥 the go-to reasons local governments offer when trying to justify sign regulations. Although courts have acknowledged these interests are 鈥渟ignificant鈥 or 鈥渟ubstantial,鈥 they have  gone so far as to accept that they are 鈥渃ompelling.鈥

The Court could have ended its analysis there. But it went a step further, assuming for the sake of argument that aesthetics and traffic safety were compelling interests, just so the Court could go on to explain that the sign code would still fail strict scrutiny because it wasn鈥檛 narrowly tailored to achieving the town鈥檚 stated interests. As to aesthetics, the Court noted that 鈥渢emporary directional signs are no greater an eyesore than ideological or political ones,鈥 yet the code allowed 鈥渦nlimited proliferation of larger ideological signs while strictly limiting the number, size, and duration of smaller directional ones.鈥

The government also can鈥檛 privilege the American flag 鈥 or even official government flags generally 鈥 over other flags

The traffic safety rationale fared no better. The town failed to show 鈥渢hat limiting temporary directional signs is necessary to eliminate threats to traffic safety, but that limiting other types of signs is not.鈥 This underinclusiveness was fatal because, as the Court pointed out, the government cannot plausibly claim strict limits on one type of sign are necessary while allowing unlimited numbers of other types of signs that create the same alleged problem.

While Reed makes clear that sign ordinances drawing content-based distinctions are almost always unconstitutional, the Court acknowledged that certain content-based rules 鈥 such as for hazard signs or street numbers 鈥 could pass strict scrutiny. But apart from narrow circumstances such as these, the government violates the First Amendment when it singles out certain topics for regulation. This means the government can鈥檛 do things like treat 鈥減olitical鈥 signs differently from other signs. The government also can鈥檛 privilege the American flag 鈥 or even official government flags generally 鈥 over other flags, either. The bottom line is that the government can鈥檛 favor one type of speech over another without a very good reason.

Andrea Dick stands before the banners and flags that led the city of Roselle Park to charge her with obscenity
A municipal court judge in New Jersey ordered homeowner Andrea Dick to remove banners containing the phrase 鈥淔uck Biden鈥 from her property or face a fine. The decision was widely derided as unconstitutional and the charges were dropped. (READ MORE)

Content-neutral sign restrictions

But what if a sign ordinance is content-neutral, meaning it doesn鈥檛 treat signs differently based on what they say? Some local governments seem to think they have carte blanche to restrict speech as long as they aren鈥檛 discriminating against particular topics or messages 鈥 including when it comes to yard signs. Fortunately, that鈥檚 not how the First Amendment works. Even content-neutral rules, that is, what courts call 鈥渢ime, place, and manner鈥 restrictions, can be unconstitutional if they unduly restrict free expression.

Although content-neutral sign ordinances do not have to advance a compelling government interest, they still face real constitutional limits. To pass muster, they must be narrowly tailored to advance a 鈥渟ignificant鈥 or 鈥渟ubstantial鈥 government interest and leave open ample alternative channels of communication. 鈥淪ignificant鈥 and 鈥渟ubstantial鈥 are lower thresholds than 鈥渃ompelling,鈥 but they still mean the government鈥檚 interest must be more than trivial. Whether a sign regulation meets this standard is always a fact-specific question.

In 蜜桃直播鈥檚 experience, problematic time, place, and manner restrictions on yard signs mainly take one of two forms: numerical limits or durational limits.

Numerical limits

Some ordinances limit how many signs can be in someone鈥檚 yard, often capping it around three. Such restrictions are usually unconstitutional because local governments can鈥檛 show they鈥檙e narrowly tailored to serve a significant interest.

The U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit, for example, held a Virginia county鈥檚 . The court questioned the county鈥檚 reliance on aesthetics as a rationale, noting the Supreme Court鈥檚 observation that, generally, 鈥減rivate property owners鈥 esthetic concerns will keep the posting of signs on their property within reasonable bounds.鈥

The Fourth Circuit also found that the county鈥檚 ordinance didn鈥檛 leave open sufficient alternative means of communication. It rejected as too time-intensive or expensive the government鈥檚 proposed alternatives like giving speeches in public places, distributing flyers, engaging in door-to-door and public canvassing, and appearing at citizen group meetings. This 鈥渓aundry list鈥 of alternatives failed to recognize how a two-sign limit infringed homeowners鈥 rights, leaving no 鈥渧iable alternative to the homeowner on his property.鈥 There鈥檚 really no substitute for a yard sign when it comes to saying what you want to say, where you want to say it. 

Does this ruling mean all numerical limits are unconstitutional? Not necessarily. If the government set the limit at a much higher number, a court might look at that limit differently. But the key takeaway is that the government has the responsibility to show its regulations are actually necessary to address a real problem.

Durational limits

Local governments also often restrict how long signs can remain on display; however, these restrictions are likely unconstitutional. 

As an example, consider an ordinance that bans having any signs up for more than three months a year. This restriction would function as an outright ban for three-quarters of the year. The U.S. Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit  an outright yard sign ban, holding it was arguably not 鈥溾榯ailored鈥 at all,鈥 let alone narrowly tailored. The same could be said of a ban that applies nine months out of the year.

Like strict numerical limits, durational limits that function as temporary bans do not leave open ample alternative channels of communication. Signs are an important 鈥 and, for many people, irreplaceable 鈥 means of expressing personal opinions. As the Supreme Court has explained, signs lack any real substitute, especially in a residential context:

Residential signs are an unusually cheap and convenient form of communication. Especially for persons of modest means or limited mobility, a yard or window sign may have no practical substitute. Even for the affluent, the added costs in money or time of taking out a newspaper advertisement, handing out leaflets on the street, or standing in front of one鈥檚 house with a hand-held sign may make the difference between participating and not participating in some public debate. Furthermore, a person who puts up a sign at her residence often intends to reach neighbors, an audience that could not be reached nearly as well by other means.

This recognition of the importance of residential signs led one lower court to  that extended durational bans are unconstitutional and 鈥渋nconsistent with the 鈥榲enerable鈥 status that the Supreme Court has accorded to individual speech emanating from an individual鈥檚 private residence.鈥

Front of Historic Franklin Theatre in Downtown Franklin, Tennessee in 2021

Franklin, Tennessee: Ordinance restricts temporary signs and flags

The town of Franklin restricts both yard signs and flags in its zoning ordinance. 蜜桃直播 wrote to city officials outlining the constitutional problems.

Read More

Sometimes durational limits take a different form. Rather than banning signs in general from remaining on display past a certain time limit, local governments may target temporary signs relating to an election or event. For example, a town might allow display of an event-related sign only up to 30 days before and two days after the event. To the extent these rules are content-based, they are likely to fail under strict scrutiny, as mentioned above, because they treat signs differently based on whether they refer to specific events.

It鈥檚 easy to see the absurdity of such rules. If a town bans campaign signs outside election season, it will have to decide whether a sign reading 鈥淲e Support the President!鈥 should be treated differently from one saying 鈥淩e-elect the President!鈥 Either the town arbitrarily singles out the latter, or it imposes an unconstitutional gag order on political speech for most of the year. Similarly, if a town requires removal of holiday signs or displays after what it views as the applicable holiday, it ends up policing whether something is really a Christmas decoration or 鈥 as 蜜桃直播 successfully dealt with in a recent case 鈥 whether it鈥檚 a covert (and illegally unseasonal) Halloween decoration.

The government has no business asking questions like these, and the First Amendment ensures it doesn鈥檛 get to.

Conclusion

Yard signs are a form of expression fully protected by the First Amendment. The government can鈥檛 restrict them just because government officials or even a majority of residents want to do so. When the government restricts people鈥檚 expression in their own yards, it needs a very good reason. Content-based restrictions generally won鈥檛 cut it. Neither will arbitrary numerical and durational restrictions. When it comes to personal expression 鈥 especially on one鈥檚 own property 鈥 the First Amendment is a 鈥渒eep out鈥 sign to government officials. 

Share